Courtesy of Life Matters Journal. This essay was published, with illustrations, in Volume 4 Issue 1 — June 2015.
I would like to thank Jake Earl, who created the “John” thought experiment. The probing questions of various people, but most definitively of Earl, helped me to better think things through.
Moral principles must be based on pre-logical moral intuitions and laws should be based on those moral principles. (Of course to say that “laws should be based on those moral principles” is not to say that every moral principle should automatically be enacted into a law.)
Though everyone I have talked to agrees that moral principles must be based on pre-logical moral intuitions, I have heard an intelligent person or two contend that the correctness of such moral intuitions can still be logically proved or disproved (by which I mean, proved by a process of discursive argumentation, if not by formal academic logic) — as if moral inquiries were a hard science like math. More importantly, many people who would not explicitly make this contention nevertheless present their arguments about moral issues as if this were the case. So while some philosopher probably demonstrated centuries ago the impossibility of logically proving the correctness of moral intuitions, the relationship of logic and intuition still deserves to be examined. And I think the insights gained in the process of examining it can lead us toward methods of self-exploration and of discourse that will help reveal moral truths, including moral truths about abortion.
First of all, for moral principles to be based on moral intuitions really means that moral principles are the verbalized form of moral intuitions. Therefore correct moral principles will follow from correct moral intuitions. And if the correctness of a moral intuition could be logically proved, then it would be possible to construct a correct moral principle through logic alone, with no recourse to intuition — since the process of constructing would be the same as the process of proving.
To say that it would be possible to construct a correct moral principle through logic alone, but at the same time to agree that moral intuitions (of which moral principles are the verbalized forms) are pre-logical — as everyone seems to agree — would be contradictory. Nevertheless, as mentioned, some people do present their arguments about moral issues as if the correctness of a moral intuition could be logically proved (that is, as if it would be possible to construct a correct moral principle through logic alone). So let’s continue to address that contention.
“The correctness of a moral intuition can be logically proved” and “a correct moral principle can be constructed through logic alone” seem to me like two different formulations of the same thing. But in case there’s any doubt, as I continue I’ll address the one I’ve actually heard, the former.
Is there such a thing as a correct moral intuition, and if so, can its correctness be logically proved or disproved? Though I am arguing no to the second question, I will argue yes to the first.
Moral Intuitions and Moral Principles
As an example of a moral principle — a generalized moral principle, but basically a sound one, I feel — let’s use “Thou shalt not kill.” I would say that that principle did not come from God, but rather is based on a pre-logical and pre-verbal human revulsion at most killing of the innocent. A pre-logical and pre-verbal sense of right or wrong is how I would define a moral intuition. Psychology professor Paul Bloom, author of the recent book Just Babies: The Origins of Good and Evil, said in an interview that while some moral ideals “are the product of culture and society” and “not in the genes,” “there also exist hardwired moral universals – moral principles that we all possess. And even those aspects of morality . . . that vary across cultures are ultimately grounded in these moral foundations.” Even if Bloom overestimates the role of the genes in the “hardwired” moral senses, and underestimates the role of culture in those moral senses, and overestimates how universal those moral senses are across cultures, it would be safe to say that most of us do have senses of right or wrong that come out of our unconscious in ways we cannot understand. I am calling those senses moral intuitions. (For alternatives to the term “moral intuition,” and for an explanation of “pre-logical” and “pre-verbal,” see Appendix A.)
I would say that the pre-logical and pre-verbal human revulsion at most killing of the innocent is an example of a correct moral intuition. I call it “correct” in that I think that deference to that intuition is necessary to the psychological health of human beings. I think that humans will sacrifice some of their psychological health (their conscience will trouble them, if you will, and they will carry around guilt, sometimes at a subconscious level) if they go against that intuition. I think that such psychological health could be measured, but let’s call the idea of measuring it just my idea, for now.
If we can accept that we are born with at least the seeds of some moral intuitions in us, then clearly those seeds are in each of us before we begin thinking logically, just as are the emotions of babies. Moral intuitions and emotions develop in us before logic, and continue to function in us pre-logically; science and logic develop in us later. And moral intuitions and emotions are both forms of caring, or “caring about.” Science and logic operate under certain rules, one of which, for both, is a commitment to dispassion. (Even discursive argumentation that is not formal academic logic is committed to dispassion.) So science and logic can tell us, in their different ways, what is, but they cannot tell us the meaning of life or convince us to care about anything. And since they cannot convince us to care, convince us that anything matters, they cannot tell us what should be. Only moral intuitions, which are a form of caring, can tell us what should be – can give us moral principles.
There is a part of our minds which cares about things, to which things matter, both emotionally and normatively. (I do not mean here “caring for,” as in “I care for my friend.”) The caring part of our minds cannot use logic, and the logical part cannot care.
Logic cannot even prove to us that right or wrong exists, much less that any action is right or wrong. So of course it cannot prove that the moral intuition that told us how to act is right or wrong, correct or incorrect. Logical thought aimed at setting moral principles is impossible without basing it on something pre-logical.
Logic can be applied to intuitions, but as a dispassionate science, it can only demonstrate the correctness of any moral intuition, if at all, with reference to some already-existing moral intuition. Tracing back in this way, we will eventually come to some moral intuition that was not arrived at through logic. It came out of our unconscious in some way we cannot understand.
Finally, the medium of logic is either words or math, while an intuition is by definition something pre-logical (and pre-verbal and pre-mathematical). Since an intuition is not framed in words or math, words and math cannot completely describe it, much less prove it right or wrong. Logic may lead us close to the door of intuition — with luck very close — but in order to pass through and feel the intuition, feel that something matters, we have to leave logic behind. As mentioned, it is only the intuition that says, “Something matters,” not the logic.
(For further elaboration of this demonstration, see Appendix A.)
We should never say, “I believe in XYZ principle for ABC reasons,” but rather, “I intuit that XYZ principle is correct, and A, B and C are likely the factors that brought me to that intuition.”
The foregoing means that all of us involved on any side of the abortion issue, as with many issues, are out advocating or marching or voting for policies that mean life or death for others, without completely knowing why we are doing so. (This does not mean that we should fail to proceed as best we can, however.)
I recently came across a thought experiment created by Jake Earl that offers an analogy to pregnancy and abortion:
While on a hike one morning in the Appalachian wilderness, John hears the screams of a child coming from the nearby river. He sees the child is clinging to a rock in the middle of the river, and will surely die without his assistance, since nobody else is around to help and John does not have the means to call emergency services. John is a decent swimmer, so he will almost certainly survive the rescue attempt, but there are still risks: the polluted water threatens to worsen John’s health in the near- and long-term, he will likely experience significant pain and discomfort in getting the child out of the river and getting him to safety, and the whole experience might be so traumatic as to send John into depression, and might damage his overall quality of life. Also, even though John is a swimmer, the river is tricky, and he faces a fundamentally unknown risk to his life if he embarks on the mission.
Now, is it obvious that John is morally obligated to do everything in his power to keep the child alive? Perhaps he [is], but I think it is in no way obvious, precisely because common sense tells us that the duty to rescue others is mitigated by certain risk factors.
Now let’s change Earl’s word “morally” to “legally” — is it obvious that John is, or rather under ideal laws should be, legally obligated?
And now suppose there is a pro-lifer, PL. PL feels sincerely that a pregnant woman should be legally prevented from aborting, so long as the woman’s risk of grave loss of well-being appears small. PL feels this deeply, but let’s say that PL’s logical powers are not strong.
A pro-choicer, PC, asks PL: Should John be legally obligated to do everything in his power to keep the child alive?
PL: Maybe not.
PC: Isn’t requiring a pregnant woman to keep her child alive parallel to requiring John to keep the child alive?
PL: I guess so, I don’t know.
PC: Then maybe a pregnant woman shouldn’t be legally required to keep her child alive?
PL: No, I think she should.
PL’s “I guess so” betrays logical inconsistency: at the same time that PL guesses — within the limits of his/her logical abilities — that two situations are morally parallel, s/he holds differing intuitions about the respective moral principles that should apply and be translated into law.
But that doesn’t necessarily mean that either intuition — the intuition about legal obligation in pregnancy or the intuition about legal obligation in a situation that seems analogous to pregnancy — is incorrect. Let’s assume they are both correct: we can understand that if they are, PL’s ineptness at debate wouldn’t make either one incorrect.
PL may not be very smart, but then no human being’s logical power is infinite. It’s quite possible that there is some subtle disanalogy between the John situation and the pregnancy situation, such that PL’s intuitions about both situations are correct; yet even if Judith Thomson, Don Marquis and Aristotle were all combined into one, they would not be able to figure out what that disanalogy was. That inability would not mean that PL’s intuitions were incorrect.
It might also be that PL’s moral intuitions about many other situations are incorrect, yet his/her intuitions about the John situation and about pregnancy are correct.
Three smart philosophical minds all rolled into one might not be able to figure out what the disanalogy is. It might be that all the logical power of the human race (which is pretty puny in absolute terms, after all) may never be able to figure out what that disanalogy is (or more likely, there is a combination of disanalogies working in different directions to result in shifting the intuitive balance one way or another). And yet PL’s John intuition and pregnancy intuition are both correct.
If all the logical power of the human race cannot figure out what the disanalogy is, then there is only one way to arrive at both correct intuitions – the direct intuitive way, not requiring logic – and there is no foolproof way to convince anyone who holds incorrect intuitions that PL’s intuitions are both correct, though in fact they are both correct. (As we are assuming here.)
I mentioned earlier, “Logic may lead us close to the door of intuition, with luck very close, but in order to pass through we have to leave logic behind.” Trying with his/her logic to compare the situation of pregnancy (in which PL feels that a pregnant woman should normally be obliged to accept the degree of risk necessary to “help” her unborn child), with the “John” situation above (in which PL feels that a hiker should not normally be obliged to take a risk to help a child), PL could not immediately find any morally relevant difference. The “John” analogy did not radically change PL’s intuition about pregnancy, but it may have nudged PL in the direction of a different intuition. If two people have differing intuitions about situation A, but one of them posits a somewhat similar situation B and another somewhat similar situation C which elicit in him the same intuition he had about A, and the other person agrees with the first person’s intuition about B and C, then the logic of the similarities/parallels may lead the second person close to the door of the same intuition on A as the first person. But that logic cannot take the second person through the door into a pre-logical realm. And if there is no situation very similar to A, then such comparison of situations may not even lead that second person very close to that particular door.
A corollary to the above would be: Everyone in the world might be logically convinced of the validity of an intuition — say PL’s intuition, on which the principle “a pregnant woman should, in many cases, be legally prevented from aborting” is based — yet the intuition could nevertheless (due to the finite nature of our logical power) be incorrect.
I think it would be true to say that you could arrive at a correct moral principle through intuition alone, without logic, but you could not arrive at a correct moral principle through logic that is not based on intuition. What causes most people to say that the kidnapped person is not obliged to lend their body to the violinist? It is not logic, but simply a direct moral intuition about that particular situation. We do not need to be told a story about a trombone player in order to have the intuition that we have about the violinist. This shows the primacy, in moral investigations, of direct intuition about a specific situation. We do not need to be told a story about a violinist in order to have a basic intuition about pregnancy.
Logic and analogies do seem to resonate somehow in our unconscious minds whence intuitions come, but by definition we do not experience what the unconscious is thinking. As PL’s example showed us, the unconscious may disagree with the best of a person’s conscious logic. It could even be that the unconscious is employing a superior logical power, but we don’t know.
In “De Facto Guardian and Abortion,” Steve Wagner, Timothy Brahm, et. al. find their pre-logical moral intuitions that Mary should be legally obligated to feed the child; then they proceed, in a section called “Making Sense of Our Intuitions,” to cogitate logically about the morally-relevant factors and to develop some taxonomy, “de facto guardian.” I am grateful for what they have done in this essay and agree with them on most of their conclusions; neither do I have an issue with this particular section. But I would like to explore the rationale for this section: If there were no plausible logical way to “make sense of their intuitions,” would that mean that the intuitions were wrong? If there were a way, but no logical power on earth could find that way, would that mean that the intuitions were wrong? If there were a way, but these particular individuals could not find the way, should they moderate the degree of their conviction about the matter? And is there ever really any need for intuition – could these authors, for instance, have come to the same moral principles through logic alone?
The opinion on this that I expressed above is “you could arrive at a correct moral principle through intuition alone, without logic, but you could not arrive at a correct moral principle through logic that is not based on intuition.” Logic can nudge me toward a certain moral intuition, correct or incorrect, but that moral intuition I have found is pre-logical and pre-verbal. It cannot be said that I have simply come to a logical conclusion.
The Practical Implications: Deeper Dialogues
Now let us see whether all my academic moral philosophy has any practical importance, particularly for the abortion debate. The origins of correct moral principles, or (if the idea of moral absolutes is not accepted) at least valuable moral principles, and the role of logic in the development of such principles, are certainly at the foundation of moral philosophy. But apart from academic moral philosophy, do the views I have stated, even if they are correct, matter?
Moral principles certainly have practical implications — in the case of the abortion issue, such principles, as translated into law or even simply as influential social norms, determine every day whether unborn babies will live and whether their mothers will have to accept unwished-for changes in their lives. So moral principles have practical implications, and I think that my views above have some practical implications as well that will help us determine the best moral principles. Some of the practical implications:
1. It is well-known that people tailor their logic to their intuitions to a large extent, and I think that much of this occurs unconsciously. If people will begin to think that neither are intuitions always disrespectable, nor is logic (on moral issues) sacred, they will become more motivated to look within at their intuitions and to try to grasp what those intuitions are and how those intuitions interact with their more conscious mental processes; the workings of their minds will become clearer to them. “Know thyself.” We are all out advocating policies that mean life or death for others, without completely knowing why we are doing so; I don’t think it is possible to know completely, but it is possible to know better, and moreover I think that the process of contemplating their existing intuitions will gradually lead people toward the most correct intuitions that reside within them.
2. If we become aware that our exploration of thought experiments, etc., is an exercise in experimenting with logic to help us find a moral intuition already existing in our unconscious – rather than an exercise in deriving a moral intuition or moral principle through logic itself – this also will motivate us to look within at our intuitions, that is, to assign a higher priority than before to the kind of contemplative approach that can move us most directly toward the deep-seated intuition.
We should not abandon our logical debates, but we should not imagine them (as we may sometimes, consciously or unconsciously) to be a process of fitting together logical jigsaw pieces to produce a case that will be finally satisfying to the left brain. We should remember always that analogies and other rational arguments function, rather, like the explosives used in surface mining. They pulverize the surface of our minds. The logic triggers mental activity that is not logical, and we get to pre-logical intuitions beneath the surface that we may not have expected. The approach may be logical in nature, but we should not expect it to achieve a result of the same nature.
3. If the representatives of both sides on any issue — say a pro-lifer and a pro-choicer on the abortion issue — can agree that the debate is really a matter of one intuition versus another, I think that this will work in two ways. On the one hand, each of the two will admit to himself that his intuition comes out of his unconscious in ways he cannot understand, and this should produce greater humility about those intuitions — not a direct weakening of the two people’s intuitions in the intuition area of their brains/minds, but rather greater humility in the pride/humility area of their brains/minds. This will reduce the ego clutter and make changes of intuition easier. Yet on the other hand, the debaters will develop greater trust in their intuitions relative to their logic, recognizing that, for better or worse, there cannot be any moral truth unsupported by intuition.
4. I think that people’s egos are more wrapped up with their logical powers than with their intuitions. If people come to realize that that which involves their egos — logic — will not ultimately prove anything or bring a discussion about a moral issue to any final conclusion, then each party in a debate might become emotionally less defensive about their logical powers, leading them to relax their egos. This also would very much reduce the clutter in their thinking processes.
5. I referred above to “looking within at their intuitions.” I would like to see a discussion between the parties on both sides of any issue — say between a pro-choicer and a pro-lifer — that begins with each party examining their own intuitions and related feelings (feelings being not exactly the same as intuitions). How does the thought of an unborn child dying in an abortion make me feel? Do I feel the pain in my body? If not, where does that feeling come from? Is it necessarily valid? How do I know it’s valid?
Then each party would try to describe those intuitions and physical-emotional feelings to the other party. A pro-lifer might say: “It pains me here [pointing probably to the chest region] to think of my innocent little unborn sister or brother, just beginning their life, being ripped apart.” A pro-choicer might say on the other hand: “It pains me here [also pointing to somewhere in the chest region] to think of my pregnant sister, already under such a burden, being told what she can or cannot do within her body.” (Using “sisters” and “brothers” in a spiritual or humanistic sense.)
(“Appeals to emotion” have a bad name. Appeals to emotion can be manipulative, but I think that an expression of one’s genuine emotion is likely to better represent one’s moral intuition than an attempt to represent it logically.)
Then the two proceed to discuss the violinist, the Cabin in the Blizzard, the “John” thought experiment, etc., at each point reporting “This makes me feel such-and-such deep inside.” If the two wish, they can logically examine the relative extents of all the analogies and disanalogies of the thought experiments as well.
At the end, each will again examine and report their direct intuition about pregnancy itself — not about any analogy with pregnancy, but about pregnancy itself. Perhaps their intuition will have changed, or will be on a slow road toward change. Each party will admit to the other, “I don’t completely know why this is my conviction.”
See also “The Psychological Morass of the Abortion Issue.”
Through a better understanding of the roles of intuition and logic in moral investigations, I think that those participating in any discussion will be able more quickly to identify the differences in intuition that separate them, and think also that each person will better realize that she cannot fully explain the origins of her own intuitions, even to herself. Moral philosophy becomes irrelevant if separated from applied psychology. I think that following the above guidelines, some of the more cerebral “moral principles” people have will fall away immediately.
The Evolution of Intuitions
In the build-up to the abolition of slavery in the US, many people intuited that slavery was wrong; but the fact that slavery was ultimately abolished doesn’t mean that it was ever proved logically to be wrong. The abolitionist intuition was not proven; it prevailed. There is now a consensus, which I agree with, that slavery is wrong — that what prevailed, in other words, was the correct intuition — but even today, if someone were to advance a logical argument saying that slavery is right, that argument could not be conclusively defeated on its own terms. What our moral intuitions regarding slavery have undergone has been a process of evolution, and our moral intuitions regarding abortion will undergo the same. The question of the morality of slavery is ultimately intractable to a logical approach, and so are questions of the morality of abortion and of abortion law.
Though I don’t know if he would agree with me about the limited role of logic, I will quote Paul Bloom again: “Good moral ideas can spread through the world in much the same way that good scientific ideas can, and once they are established, people marvel that they could ever have thought differently.”
Sam Harris’s The Moral Landscape presents an argument — which I am open to with a few exceptions — that the neuroscience of the future could measure the well-being of a population, and see how that well-being responds to variations in the moral principles of the population, accurately enough to determine scientifically which moral principles are best. This all presupposes a consequentialist definition of “best,” which I’m open to, but in any case the reality of this approach lies too far in the future to be useful to us now. For now we can only try to find our best moral intuitions.
Someone on the pro-choice side will likely say that my arguments, coming as they do from a pro-lifer, confess to a weakness of logic on the pro-life side. Fine. Such an assertion would not diminish the power of any good logic or good intuitions on any side.
© 2014
Appendix A: Some further thoughts, added June 2016, on the above LMJ essay –
Apart from the comments in the Leave a Reply section below, some readers have responded to “Moral Intuition, Logic, and the Abortion Debate” on other websites or on Facebook.
A few of them have questioned the term “moral intuition;” one would have preferred “moral seeming,” and another would have preferred “moral sense,” either of which is acceptable to me.
Some have asked about “pre-logical” and “pre-verbal”. One wrote: I am not sure what you mean by “moral intuitions . . . develop in us before logic, and continue to function in us pre-logically . . .”
I replied: “Let me take just the ‘function’ part, and skip the ‘develop’ part. Suppose you see an innocent person being tortured in front of you, perhaps by a serial torturer-killer. A number of things will happen before (pre-) you start thinking about it logically and verbally: You will feel disgust (which if put in words would be ‘How gross to see that child’s fingernails being ripped out’). Fear: ‘I don’t want that guy to do that to me.’ Maybe anger. Annnd . . . a sense of right or wrong, in this case wrong. All these things are pre-logical and pre-verbal, and the last is your pre-logical, pre-verbal moral intuition.”
Some readers also had difficulty with “caring,” as in “The caring part of our minds cannot use logic, and the logical part cannot care.” Some readers have misunderstood “caring” here as “caring for,” as in “I care for my friend.” But I mean “caring about;” that is, I mean that things matter to me. (I have now edited that passage in the essay above.) I wrote to one reader:
“First let’s distinguish between moral intuitions and emotion. Suppose that tomorrow morning I read in the news that half a million people in Sub-Saharan Africa are expected to die of starvation within a month. And suppose that on that same morning I drop my cell phone and it breaks. I may be more upset about the cell phone than about the starvation. That upsetness is an example of feeling/emotion.
“But if you tell me, ‘Your cell phone can be saved or the half million people can be saved, you have to decide,’ an inner voice will tell me that the half million people should be saved, and I will follow that voice. That voice is my moral intuition about that particular situation.
“But (until we think of a better word than ‘caring’) I am saying ‘moral intuitions and emotions are both forms of caring. Science and logic operate under certain rules, one of which, for both, is a commitment to dispassion,’ because both my moral intuitions and my emotions make me feel that something matters. An emotion may make me feel that something is ‘unpleasant.’ A moral intuition may make me feel that something is ‘wrong.’ Either way, it matters, I care. Whereas when I’m using the scientific or logical part of my mind, the things I am thinking about do not matter.”
Moral philosophy operates on the basis of all kinds of inputs from all fields, including psychology. Much of “Moral Intuition, Logic, and the Abortion Debate” is about psychological realities as I see them. I would request readers to think of the above paragraphs in this appendix, and much of what now follows, as pure psychology, which I’ll try to tie in with moral philosophy later. Some readers did not understand my epistemological point about the limitations of logic and discursive argumentation. What now follows is a reply of mine (slightly adapted) to one reader:
Suppose you are trying to convince me that abortion, at least in cases other than rape cases, is wrong. Suppose we have been debating for days with all kinds of analogies (logic) and science and statistics. Then you point out to me something I never thought of before: that when a couple have sex, they know not only that that may create a baby, but that if it does, it will create a baby that is in a unique dependent condition. You have used some logic, or at least dispassionate discursive argumentation.
A moment later or a month later I am thinking about that and I feel a shift in my mind. For the first time I have a moral intuition (or moral seeming, or moral sense) which if verbalized would be “Abortion is wrong.”
Now, I may think “That moral intuition PROBABLY stems from the thing about the unique dependent condition.” But since my moral intuition, my should-shouldn’t sense, is itself pre-logical (if I am confronted with a specific proposed abortion, I will feel “This is wrong” before [pre-] I start thinking about it logically and verbally), I don’t know for sure what the provenance of that moral intuition was. Ultimately it came out of my unconscious in some way I can’t completely understand. It might actually have resulted from taking LSD or from a bump on the head, not from your logic about dependency.
For me, it’s like I have two little men operating in the conscious level of my mind. One little man N (for intuition) operates at a pre-verbal level. Like a newborn baby, he has no vocabulary. But he has a gut sense, or intuition, about the morality of abortion. That sense is not an emotion. (I no doubt have some more little men in me emoting about abortion, but let’s ignore them for now.) That intuition, if it were to be expressed in words, would be the words “This is wrong,” and I would then have a moral principle, “Abortion is wrong.” But for now (considering only man N), I just have a pre-verbal moral intuition. I have no clue as to the provenance of that intuition. Presumably it is coming out of my unconscious. Yet that intuition is real knowledge of what is right and what is wrong, and, I am arguing, it is the only real knowledge possible for me of what is right and what is wrong. The only real knowledge possible for me of what is right and what is wrong is a pre-logical intuition whose provenance, rational or otherwise, I cannot understand.
The other little man L (for logic) has a vocabulary and can say things like “Killing innocent human beings is wrong. An unborn baby is an innocent human being. Therefore killing unborn babies is wrong.” But that little man is operating dispassionately, and though he is applying logic to the situation, he himself is incapable of feeling “should” or “shouldn’t” and thus cannot have real knowledge of what is right and what is wrong.
L can understand N, but only in a theoretical way. N can’t directly understand L at all. (IF L’s logic sinks into my unconscious and is in fact instrumental in the origin of N’s newfound moral intuition, then we can say that N has indirectly understood L. But I don’t really know if that has happened in me or not.) So we cannot say that N’s moral sense came from L’s logic.
Getting back to my original epiphany that abortion is wrong: Let’s suppose that my newfound moral intuition (the domain of man N) underlying the moral principle “Abortion is wrong” is a correct moral intuition. If its provenance was a rational method at all, that rational method unfolded in my unconscious (man N did not gain that intuition from man L, whom he can’t understand). I don’t really know what that method was. Since I don’t really know from what rational method, if any, that moral intuition derived, I can’t be sure that any rational method (employed by man L) in my conscious mind that leads to the principle “Abortion is wrong” is a correct method. It might be the same, correct, method employed in my unconscious mind, or it might be a method containing some fault we haven’t noticed, that came to the correct conclusion “Abortion is wrong” by luck. We neither know that it is the same, correct, method employed in my unconscious mind, nor know that it contributed to my having that moral intuition. And therefore we don’t know whether it could contribute to anyone’s “man N” having that intuition; and since it is only everyone’s man N that represents real moral knowledge, we don’t know whether that rational method establishes the moral principle.
So in terms of moral epistemology, unless we can trust some scripture to provide correct moral principles, the only reliable way for any person to arrive at such a principle is to experience personally a moral intuition that underlies that moral principle. That person will be unable to conclusively demonstrate the correctness of the moral principle or the moral intuition to any other person. But every person is capable of finding that correct moral intuition within themselves. And just as a certain rational method PROBABLY helped nudge me to the correct moral intuition (in the above scenario), rational methods can PROBABLY help nudge others.
I would submit that anyone who attributes their conviction about any moral principle to a rational method, doesn’t really know for sure that that rational method is what accounts for their conviction. Therefore they don’t know whether that rational method could bring anyone to that conviction; therefore they don’t know whether that rational method establishes the moral principle.
Remember that I’m talking mostly psychology here. If you think the psychology is wrong, challenge me on that, but let’s try to agree on the psychology before again bringing in other aspects of moral philosophy.
I think that all this has practical consequences for how we can best dialogue – consequences set out in the above essay under The Practical Implications: Deeper Dialogues.
Appendix B: Some further thoughts, added July 2017, on the above LMJ essay –
An outline of an argument for the view that CORRECT moral intuitions are ultimately the only way to know moral truth:
It seems to me that it is only because of our pre-logical senses, or intuitions, of right and wrong that the words “right” and “wrong” mean anything to us in the first place. When someone says, “It is wrong to do X!” we momentarily have a certain physical and psychic sensation of wrongness (not the same thing as an emotion) that can’t be captured in words or in math. And when someone says, “It is right to do X!” we momentarily have a different physical and psychic sensation that can’t be captured in words or in math. (And when we stop and assess X for ourselves, we end up with some sensation of the rightness or wrongness of X that can’t be captured in words or in math.)
So when I, for my part, say that action X or Y is wrong, I may, and probably do, mean that action X or Y has an objective property of wrongness, but I CERTAINLY mean (or mean as well) that the action should ideally trigger in anyone the sensation of wrongness with which I am experientially familiar. If not for having experienced that sensation, “wrong” would not mean anything to me. Trying to reason out what “wrong” means would be like trying to reason out what “green” means. It might be best to call what it means a kind of qualia.
Now, I may say that failing to kidnap a homeless person and harvest his organs would be wrong because some professor has convinced me intellectually that it is wrong, without really feeling the sensation of wrongness. Nevertheless, I could not meaningfully say that it is wrong unless I had at least felt the sensation of wrongness in some other context. The word “wrong” ultimately means that which will, as an objective fact, trigger that sensation in someone who has sufficient capacity for correct moral intuitions.
Up till this point, we still have not gotten to one statement that I would like to make now: “The triggering of that sensation, that moral intuition, can correctly identify a wrong act.” (And we will never get to the statement “The triggering of that sensation necessarily DOES identify a wrong act,” because not every occurrence of that sensation identifies a wrong act. Sometimes moral intuitions are not perfectly reliable and sometimes people disagree about them.)
The statement “The triggering of that sensation, that moral intuition, can correctly identify a wrong act (or identify moral truth)” would be false if:
1. there is no objective moral truth. I believe many scientists think that there is no objective moral truth, and that we have been equipped with SENSATIONS of moral truth because those sensations have evolutionary adaptive value. This is possible.
2. there is objective moral truth (which I believe for reasons not all of which I will get into here), but no one’s sensations/intuitions about moral truth actually identify moral truths with more than random success. This is also possible, but seems so unlikely to me given that it is only those sensations that make moral truth meaningful to us, that I conclude that if there is objective moral truth, then “The triggering of a sensation of wrongness, a moral intuition, can correctly identify a wrong act (or identify moral truth).”
But is a moral intuition the ONLY way to correctly identify a wrong act? If a moral intuition can in fact correctly identify a wrong act, it does so through a direct apprehension of the wrongness, whereas, since “wrong” is meaningful only as it refers to our pre-logical, pre-rational experience, any process of reasoning about whether an act is wrong may succeed, but to do so it will have to be based on some prior moral intuition about wrongness. Moral intuition at some point cannot be dispensed with.
I said a little earlier that moral intuitions are not perfectly reliable. This is very true, but I think that CORRECT moral intuitions are perfectly reliable. I think that we have to dig for those correct moral intuitions. Thought experiments and logic are very helpful, but I think that meditation and a selfless lifestyle are also necessary. Finding correct moral intuitions is part of a process of developing character. I think that only persons of exceptional character really know right from wrong. There is no easy way.
In the case of the abortion issue, knowing right from wrong may sometimes be still more difficult because some people, though unselfish, have incorrect “ontological intuitions” about the moral status of the unborn. I won’t get further into that here.
All this has profound implications for dialogue. Though much can be accomplished on the intellectual level, I think that for a bedrock conviction of the wrongness of abortion (which I don’t think all pro-lifers have), character development is needed, as well as finding the correct ontological intuition about the unborn.
Appendix C: Some further thoughts, added October 2017, on the above LMJ essay –
Our moral intuitions come out of our unconsciouses in some way we cannot understand. But I observe that when due to new information the consequences that my conscious mind foresees for some action change, I am likely to find in myself a different moral intuition about the action than I had found before. So I feel sure that my unconscious does not overlook the consequences that my conscious mind foresees. 1) It’s possible that my unconscious mind considers only those consequences in deciding what moral intuition to send to my conscious mind. 2) It’s also possible that my unconscious mind considers those consequences and considers in addition consequences that it foresees but my conscious mind doesn’t foresee. (If when I fall asleep I tell myself with enough concentration to wake up at a certain time, I will wake up at that exact time, so my unconscious mind knows things that my conscious mind doesn’t. I don’t think my unconscious mind fails to consider any expectation of consequences that is available to my conscious mind; it considers as much or more.) My unconscious mind may be a utilitarian acting under scenario 1 or scenario 2, or it may in addition take into account principles unrelated to consequences. But at least I feel sure that it doesn’t overlook consequences.
Appendix D: Some further thoughts, added January 2018, on the above LMJ essay –
I think that absent a religious grounding, our pre-logical moral intuitions provide the only possible grounding for correct moral principles / basic beliefs. I have tried to resolve this dilemma in a few essays, but here I’m going to describe my approach from a somewhat different angle than I’ve used before in order to keep it most simple:
1. Correct moral principles are the principles supported by correct moral intuitions.
2. The most correct moral intuitions are the moral intuitions of the most morally-developed people. Only a moral person can deeply understand morality.
3. Anyone can develop morally through a determination to do so and a willingness to change, and constant thinking and discussion about morality, and a selfless lifestyle, and meditation.
4. Morally-developed people will tend to recognize each other, and their moral intuitions will increasingly converge as they develop.
5. Morally-developed people will not be able to convince others through any rational process. The only way for anyone to recognize moral truth is as in 3 above.
I wrote in the LMJ essay:
I would say that the pre-logical and pre-verbal human revulsion at most killing of the innocent is an example of a correct moral intuition. I call it “correct” in that I think that deference to that intuition is necessary to the psychological health of human beings. I think that humans will sacrifice some of their psychological health (their conscience will trouble them, if you will, and they will carry around guilt, sometimes at a subconscious level) if they go against that intuition.
And I wrote in “Dismantling the Bodily-Rights Argument without Using the Responsibility Argument”:
I would use the following framework to think about the psychology of morality:
The highest good that human beings can achieve is transcendent experience – whether we speculate about that experience in the way that materialists do, as purely the functions of neurons, or in the way that spiritualists do, as a deepened apprehension of a non-material soul, or communion with a non-material higher power – and whether or not we think that such experience culminates in any final enlightenment or salvation.
A prerequisite for transcendent experience is the expansive peace of a clean conscience, which may also be called the next-highest good that human beings can achieve.
To achieve a perfectly clean conscience, our behavior must be consistent with certain moral values that are innate in all of us at a deep intuitive level, whether we interpret those values and those levels of the mind materialistically or spiritually. As mentioned in 1 above, I use “moral absolutes” to refer interchangeably to the innate values, or to the principles of conduct that they imply on an intuitive, pre-verbal, level (correct moral intuitions), or to the principles on a verbal level. Different philosophies and scientific theories may interpret in different ways how those values got there and how they may fit into any cosmic design, but anyway we are stuck with them. If we follow those moral values and adhere to the practical moral principles that they imply, we can move in the direction of transcendent experience. If our behavior departs from those values, we come in conflict those values. If we are in conflict with them, even if our conscious minds are not aware of them, our conscious minds will nevertheless be disturbed. (While if our conscious minds hold incorrect moral intuitions because we have not discovered the deeper correct ones, and we depart from those incorrect intuitions, the mind may also feel guilty and disturbed, but I think less so.)
A moral intuition, correct or incorrect, is a pre-logical and pre-verbal sense of right or wrong that comes out of our unconscious in some way we cannot understand.
It is well-known that worrying about oneself makes one unhappy, while self-forgetfulness constitutes a liberation from those worries, and makes one happy even in adverse circumstances. (We so often hear, correctly, that the main recipe for happiness in life is to lose oneself in a greater cause.) Fear is unpleasant in itself and causes sensory and cognitive shutdown, i.e., contraction of our experience, so this psychological reality (freedom from selfish worry equates to happiness) is not difficult to understand. A high degree of self-forgetfulness results in transcendent experience, the greatest happiness. We of course want that happiness, and I think that we are born with correct moral intuitions (which normally require some digging in order to access) such that “If we follow those moral values and adhere to the practical moral principles that they imply, we can move in the direction of transcendent experience” – which will entail becoming more and more selfless.
While a deliberate effort to engage in selfless behavior can be a cause of transcendent experience, it can also be an effect of transcendent experience. But for my focus here, the grounding of correct moral principles, what matters is that it is a cause of transcendent experience. The extent to which the effect occurs is a measure of the correctness of a moral principle.
While we are motivated, by a quest for happiness, to become more and more selfless, we are also born with strong selfish tendencies, sometimes supported (until we dig deeply enough) by incorrect moral intuitions. There is a constant tension or tug-of-war within us between selfish tendencies, which our correct moral intuitions tell us are wrong, and selfless tendencies, which our correct moral intuitions tell us are right.
Why are we born with correct moral intuitions, and how does it all work? I think it is like this: Evolution has programmed living beings such that adaptive behavior, behavior that helps us survive and propagate our genes, produces happiness. The immediate, proximate motivation for all the behavior of living beings is happiness. But it is also possible, though it seems (at least on the face of it) incompatible with evolutionary theory, that happiness, perhaps a special kind of happiness that might exist, might motivate some actions that are not adaptive for the individual, actions that either do not help an individual survive and propagate their genes, or actually militate against that (while helping an individual achieve something else).
The proximate motivation for all the behavior of living beings is happiness, but happiness can motivate both selfish and selfless actions, so, with happiness as a constant motivator, there is, as mentioned, a constant tension or tug-of-war within us between selfish tendencies and selfless tendencies. Transcendent experience is the greatest happiness, and may be a special kind of happiness. In any case, the happiness of transcendence is produced in a different way (selfless actions) than the happiness of normal gratifications (selfish actions). Thus the tug-of-war inside us between selfish tendencies and selfless tendencies is also a tug-of-war between a longing for transcendence (and/or happiness produced by effecting the welfare of others) and a longing for normal gratifications.
We all continually long for happiness, and have a sense of a perfect and enduring and fulfilling happiness that eludes our grasp. But it normally takes a lot of time and experience to learn that the greatest happiness is attainable when we see the futility of the selfish search for normal sources of happiness, i.e., for normal but frustratingly fleeting and limited self-gratifications, and abandon or at least curtail that search (which does not mean that we will reject normal happinesses when we come across them, by the way). We all have a longing to go beyond, to find a perfect happiness, but we are likely to bark up many wrong trees of normal self-gratifications before we settle on a search for transcendent experience through selflessness.
As I have already hinted, I think the tug-of-war between selfless tendencies / transcendence, on the one hand, and selfless tendencies / normal gratifications on the other hand, can certainly be explained at least in part by Neo-Darwinian evolutionary theory and brain structures constructed by evolution. But it becomes a little puzzling to explain it all in that way.
The longing for normal gratifications is easy to explain in evolutionary terms. Those of our ancestors who were imbued with capacities for gratification by food, sex and various kinds of comfort – those of our ancestors who derived pleasure from those things – survived and gave birth to us, while any contemporaries they might have had without those capacities did not survive.
The longing for transcendence is harder to explain. But evolution may have brought about the pleasure that some specific function, such as eating nourishing food, gives us, by designing us with a non-specific pleasure/happiness center in our brains, or if not a center, a “happiness configuration of synapses.” And it may just be a fact not achieved by the evolutionary culling process, but just by default, that whenever we are completely free from fear (our most normal forms of fear being our selfish worries), we feel happiness. This may be the secret underlying the happiness that we find in meditation – by steering our attention away from our sense of self, we automatically cease to have selfish worries, and find happiness.
And if we have some intimation of the possibility of that happiness – even if it were an unconscious intimation, but I think we all have some conscious intimation – then, assuming that experiences of that happiness are of evolutionary adaptive value, we as a species may have begun to develop conscious or unconscious impulses (moral intuitions) toward the kind of altruistic, self-sacrificing attitudes (with their consequent self-sacrificing behavior) that would result in freedom from fear, including selfish worries.
Whatever is selfless we sense as right. Whatever is selfish but does no harm to oneself or others (for instance eating to stay alive, without any intention to use one’s life for others, but without depriving others of food) is neutral, and whatever is selfish and harms oneself or others (for instance taking food from others) we sense as wrong. And this is an objective morality – those senses of right and wrong, those moral intuitions, are correct, because selflessness entails freedom from fear and therefore leads to transcendent experience, the greatest happiness. Right and wrong are objectively grounded on transcendent happiness, the highest good that human beings can achieve. It is the highest good that human beings can achieve, both for its own sake and as both a cause of and an inspiration of altruistic behavior. It causes altruistic behavior by evoking love for all living beings.
An objective moral truth is a moral intuition which, if we find it in ourselves and adhere to it in our actions, will help us to attain transcendent experiences, the greatest good in life.
The best way to lose one’s fears for oneself is to lose one’s sense of self. The most focused way to achieve this is meditation.
You may leave a reply, if you wish, without giving your name or email address. If you do give your email address, it will not be published. Back up your work as you type, in case of accidents.
Some future posts:
Life Panels
Evolution, and the Humanizing and Uplifting Effect on Society of a Commitment to the Unborn
A Trade-Off of a Sensitive Nature
Unborn Child-Protection Legislation, the Moral Health of Society, and the Role of the American Democratic Party
The Motivations of Aborting Parents
Why Remorse Comes too Late
The Kitchen-Ingredients Week-After Pill
Unwanted Babies and Overpopulation
The Woman as Slave?
Abortion and the Map of the World
While thinking about moral in general and how it works in us humans an interesting idea came to mind, later I remembered your post on moral intuition and realized that the concept I’m about to introduce is very similar to yours. Here I’ll expand a little on your ideas, hope you’ll appreciate it.
Here are the basic ideas I’ll expand on a little later :
1) Human act and think based on emotions, emotions effect everything we do.
2) All moral is ultimately derived from emotions.
3) Around moral we build abstract moral concepts.
1) The first one is pretty self-explanatory, rationality can’t tell us what the meaning of life is, it can’t make decisions for us, it can’t tell us how to live our life. All of these are done by our emotions. Rationality can help us understand the world and with it effect our emotions, but it can’t tell us what we should do with our knowledge of the world.
2) When I say that moral is “ultimately derived from emotions”, I mean that emotions can dictate moral in two ways, directly or indirectly. In a direct way emotions can tell us directly that something is moral or immoral, this sense of moral we can call “moral intuition”. In an indirect way emotions can tell us what moral constructs and principle we should accept, this way of creating moral we can call “abstract moral” or “philosophical moral”.
3) When we have something purely emotional, like moral or arts, humans have a tendency to make abstractions around it i. e. to rationalize it. In moral we build abstract moral concepts, but the basis for all of them are our emotions e. g. say we agree that doing harm to someone is immoral, now that we have established that we can declare that every person has “a right not to be harmed” and that breaking that right is immoral, this just happens to be the way things occure in reality. First the majority agrees about something, then we make an abstraction about it. So why do people do that? Well, the meaning of such abstractions are to better express our emotions and ideas, and to rationalize them. Is should be noted that people have a hard time accepting that everything we do is emotional and that our rationality is very limited thus we tend to rationalize everything we do, our fears, our wishes, our deeds, our emotions, our beliefs… Ask anyone why they fear/wish/do/believe something and they will always give you a reason, many times we ourselfs are not even aware of the fact that we are only rationalizing something and moral is no different. Relevant constructs include “reproductive rights”, “bodily rights”, “a right to life” and “personhood”.
Let us now discuss the imlications od these ideas. First of all I’d like to disclaim that idea number 3) implies that the abstract moral concepts are meaningless or useless because it doesn’t. What it does imply is that these moral concepts are a bad starting point of any moral discussion. It makes no sense to discuss moral indirectly through abstraction instead of directly through emotion. But how do we discuss moral “through emotion”? Well, as I said earlier understanding a certain moral situation plays an important role in shaping how we feel about that subject. This would mean getting the facts straight first is very important. After that we should make sure that everyone understands how moral functions in humans, the three ideas above, and understands why and how we are going to approach this discussion, what I’m writing here. And finaly we should discuss in detail how and why does every aspect of the moral sitation make us feel the way it does. Thought experiments and digressions on other moral subjects are very helpfull in this last step. And what about moral concepts like “bodily rights” and “personhood”? Well, they should also be discussed, but only after the first three steps because they do not play a vital role in this discussion as so many might think.
And with this I end this post. I hope you will help me build these ideas further, they truly are important, and adress every aspect of this discussion to make a convincing case for what we fell and know is true. Cheers.
I’m very happy to hear from someone who apparently sees the limitations of logic, and the primacy of intuition or emotion, in moral investigations, basically the same way I do.
Before continuing with this reply of mine — I like your phrase “rationality can’t tell us what the meaning of life is” and would like to request your permission to adapt it a little and borrow it. I had written in my post:
“Just as science can tell us what is, but cannot tell us what should be, logic also cannot tell us what should be. It cannot determine moral principles or prove the correctness of moral principles or intuitions.”
If you don’t mind, I would like to edit that to read:
“Just as science can tell us what is, but cannot tell us what should be, logic also cannot tell us what should be. It cannot tell us the meaning of life. It cannot determine moral principles or prove the correctness of moral principles or intuitions.”
“I hope you will help me build these ideas further”
I look forward to discussing these matters with you, with a view, as you say, to make a convincing case for what we feel and know is true. We should probably go through what you have written slowly, almost one sentence at a time. But as the first step, let’s make sure that all the terms we’re using mean the same thing to both of us, so that we’re sure of talking the same language. For example, I think you may sometimes be using the word “emotions” to mean what I mean by “intuitions;” whereas I make a distinction between the two words. You have written:
“In a direct way emotions can tell us directly that something is moral or immoral, this sense of moral has we can call ‘moral intuition’.”
Do you mean “In a direct way emotions can tell us directly that something is moral or immoral; when emotions function like this, we can call those emotions “moral intuitions” — ?
In order to illustrate how I distinguish between “emotion” and “intuition,” let me try an example: Suppose that tomorrow morning I read in the news that half a million people in Sub-Saharan Africa are expected to die of starvation within a month. And suppose that on that same morning I drop my cell phone and it breaks.
I may be more upset about the cell phone than about the starvation. That upsetness is an example of what I mean by emotions. But if you tell me, “Your cell phone can be saved or the half million people can be saved, you have to decide,” an inner voice will tell me that the half million people should be saved, and I will follow that voice. That voice is my moral intuition. Though I may be feeling emotions at the same time, my moral intuition itself doesn’t raise my blood pressure or make my stomach muscles tense as some emotion might.
I won’t insist that my definitions of words are the correct ones, but let’s make sure we’re talking the same language. Do you agree with me that there is a difference between the emotional reaction about the phone, and the sense of right and wrong? I call the first “emotions,” and the second “moral intuition.” But if you agree with me about the difference, you can suggest other words if you’d like. The words are negotiable.
In my post I wrote: “Since feelings (such as caring) and intuitions are both pre-logical, intuitions are closely connected to feelings.” In this post I use “feelings” and “emotions” interchangeably. Some psychologists make a distinction, but that may not be necessary for this discussion.
I’m glad to hear from you. There are some exciting ideas I’d like to share with you, but they don’t necessarily involve this discussion. However they are important beacuse these ideas have shaped me and my views on the world.
First off, I agree with your distinction between “emotions / feelings” and “intuition”, I can see the difference and we can use the names you’ve given them.
Also I made a typo in the next sentence, the word [has] should not be there: “In a direct way emotions can tell us directly that something is moral or immoral, this sense of moral [has] we can call ‘moral intuition’.” Wondering if you could fix that.
Furthermore I’m just glad to help, you can use my phrasing and ideas as much as you want.
And now, the exciting ideas. First I’ll share with you an article that I’d like you to read very carefully.The article is about “The Purpose of Life” and is very well writen and interesting. While reading it I’d like you to pay attention to the part “Knowing What’s Important to You”. We can discuss this article later. Here’s the link:
http://www.girlschase.com/content/purpose-life-practical-point-view
As you might that site named “Girlschase” is actually about becoming a more attractive male, I’m male so, you know… Now, I do not know if you’re male or female, but if you do go and look around the site, I just hope that you won’t be insulted or anything, the authors are not bad people wanting bad things, they just know that the world isn’t always the way we want it to be so they accept the world and adapt to it, it wasn’t an easy realisation for them either. I don’t necessarily agree with everything they say, but with some ideas I do. The site is very well made and I recommend it if you want to understand how male-female interactions work or in general how social interactions and people work.
But let’s get back to the topic, do read the article about the meaning of life so that we can talk again. Looking forward to hearing from you.
I’m male and heterosexual. At this stage in my life, I’m not looking for dating advice as such, though at one time I could have used all the help I could get.
“if you want to understand how male-female interactions work or in general how social interactions and people work.” I’m interested in everything about human behavior. At this point I have only read, in the article, “Knowing What’s Important to You.”
The author gives some examples of what might be “important to you”:
– you want to find a way to make math more appealing for school students too.
– you want to find a way to grow patients replacement parts using their own body cells.
One of these two examples involves changes in academic systems, the other involves scientific research aimed at changes in some people’s lives. The author seems to be thinking of “What’s Important to You” in terms of “What needs changing that I want to be involved in.”
Then he helps each of us to identify what each of us wants to be involved in. Here I think he makes a big contribution. Here he includes one question that seems to be deeply philosophical — “At its most core, why are things the way they are, and how do I change that?” — but he probably doesn’t mean “Why is the universe the way it is?” He probably just means “Once I have decided what needs changing, how do I understand why that thing is wrong in the first place?”
Then he says that in order to understand why that thing is wrong in the first place, “look for [the] structural problems.”
Now let’s try to think about how this can help us with a topic that you and I have been gravitating toward: the meaning of life.
I think the author has a good point that different things and experiences of the world make different people happy. If those things or experiences involve useful changes in society, it would be normal to say, “I’m doing something that I feel has meaning.”
But I would add that all human beings, and for that matter many if not all animals as well, find themselves caught up in an unavoidable struggle, from one moment to the next, their entire waking lives, to get happiness and avoid pain. For people with noble dispositions, making a meaningful contribution to society is one important source of happiness. But other people may not seek happiness in that way. Some people mainly just want to find someone who loves them. For a hungry person, at the moment he is hungry, happiness is food.
So I would say that the most meaningful thing in life, if it is possible, would be a guaranteed way to find happiness, however one may find it.
The most common ways to seek happiness (most people try a combination of these ways) involve securing physical comfort, and securing physical pleasures including sex and nice food; securing money and other physical possessions; gaining power; winning the love or at least appreciation of other people (or perceived appreciation, including perceptions of ways to make people appreciate our memory after we are gone); the company of friends; gaining a sense of achievement in terms of abilities or accomplishments; exercising the skills that one has learned; obtaining esthetic pleasures — the esthetic appreciation of art or nature, or the pleasure of artistic creativity (and also the pleasure of humor); obtaining the pleasure of scientific or other intellectual understanding. And then there are psychoactive substances. Of course people have different tastes in all these things. Mozart may not make one person happy at all, but may make another very happy.
But I said, “the most meaningful thing in life, if it is possible, would be a guaranteed way to find happiness.” None of the above things are guaranteed. And even if we get those things, the happiness is not guaranteed. We eventually get tired of any particular thing. A particular song may make us very happy twenty times, but after that, we get diminishing returns.
However, how is it that all these things bring us happiness? Some nice-tasting ice cream, for instance, is not made out of happiness. (Look at the ingredients. You won’t find happiness.) The DVD that you insert with some film or game is not made out of happiness. The ice cream and the DVD are just keys to happiness. The happiness is something that occurs inside ourselves, and all the things that we are constantly running after merely switch on the happiness (if we are lucky).
Meditation is a technique for finding the happiness within that does not depend on all the external “keys.” There is no harm if we keep pursuing those keys, but if we depend on them for happiness, we will experience a lot of frustration. We should pursue them, but not depend on them for happiness.
The kinds of “keys” to happiness that the author suggests are great. They benefit others, and because our objectives with those kinds of keys are not selfish, we do not feel personally frustrated in case we fail. But I think that even in tying our happiness to those serviceful kinds of activities, it is best to balance our work with meditation at the same time.
Greetings again,
You have presented some interesting ideas, I’ll have to contemplate on them a bit. I’ll let you know when I have something interesting.
In the meantime here are some interesting articles for you:
These two are very important:
http://www.girlschase.com/content/sprezzatura-effort-and-investing
http://www.girlschase.com/content/law-least-effort
About mentalities:
http://www.girlschase.com/content/your-mental-model-flawed
http://www.girlschase.com/content/how-victim-mentality-can-stifle-your-life-%E2%80%93-and-luck-women
http://www.girlschase.com/content/how-overcome-depression
About sociology:
http://www.girlschase.com/content/whats-wrong-dating-america-and-much-west
http://www.girlschase.com/content/conflict-between-men-and-women-21st-century
http://www.girlschase.com/content/you%E2%80%99re-not-special-and-neither-she
http://www.girlschase.com/content/navigating-culture-me
Greeting again,
I’m just here to share some very interesting articles I’ve found about the prolife cause. Of course be critical and open minded while reading this. Here they are:
http://www.uncommondescent.com/intelligent-design/libby-anne-portrait-of-an-atheist-feminist/
http://www.uncommondescent.com/intelligent-design/libby-anne-part-2-the-ethics-of-a-feminist-atheist/
http://www.uncommondescent.com/intelligent-design/libby-anne-part-3-a-reply-to-her-article-how-i-lost-faith-in-the-pro-life-movement/
The first one is about intelligent design, although some aspects are interesting I haven’t found it very persuasive for theism but rather for agnosticism, but the other two articles are the interesting ones regarding abortion.
Thanks. I’ve been very much tied up with a few things, including some pro-life work on the ground, and it will still be some time before I can look at all those articles carefully. Right now I would like to make an initial reply about your 3rd link. If I can reply more thoroughly later on, about that link and the other two, would you like me to notify you by email when I do reply (if in fact the email address you have given is a real one)?
I started with the 3rd link because it relates to the one writing by Libby Anne that I was already familiar with — her “How I Lost Faith.” It appears to me on my initial look at vjtorley’s article that he or she does a great job of dismantling that “How” writing.
In spite of vjtorley’s pointing out so many fallacies in that writing, however, he/she doesn’t seem to have addressed the fallacy that first jumped out at me: the confusion of statistical correlation for causality.
Though vjtorley criticizes Libby Anne’s reliance on statistics that calculate abortion rates as #-of-abortions/population instead of #-of-abortions/#-of-pregnancies, he/she doesn’t seem to mention that even those #-of-abortions/population statistics only show that that rate is higher where abortion is restricted, but don’t show, as Libby Anne claimed, that that rate is higher because abortion is restricted.
LA got her statistics from a magazine article about a study in the Lancet medical journal. She apparently didn’t read the study itself. The study was headed up by a Guttmacher Institute person. The Guttmacher Institute is associated with Planned Parenthood and is pro-choice, and the study was written such a way as to imply to the unwary that greater restrictions cause more abortion; but being an academic study, the authors did make it clear in the fine print they had not found any such causal relation.
What the study showed, probably correctly, is simply that poor regions of the world have more restrictions and more abortions, while rich regions of the world have less restrictions and less abortions. But there are a host of differing variables between poor regions and rich regions, one of which is better contraception in the rich regions. And in fact upon reading the study carefully, we find that the authors suggest that variable and only that variable (without quite committing even to that variable) as offering a causal explanation.
The magazine article about the study implied a bit more strongly than did the study itself that greater restrictions cause more abortion, but avoided committing itself; only LA committed herself to that unscientific interpretation.
I remember having communicated with at least four pro-choicers who had encountered the statistics of the study indirectly, either through LA or through some other source, and had subscribed to the causal interpretation. Besides pointing out the fallacy, I suggested using common sense and asking this question: If abortion restrictions really did cause more abortions, what would be the causal mechanism by which that would work? Exactly how would restrictive laws motivate parents to kill unborn children whom they had longed to keep? No one replied to that question.
In terms of any rigorousness or cogency, “How I Lost Faith” does not really deserve a long, careful response such as that of vjtorley, but perhaps in terms of its influence on gullible people, vjtorley thought such a response was necessary.
Indeed, I was familiar with that aspect of that article (cum hoc ergo propter hoc fallacy), the email I have given you isn’t real so if you want discuss with me other aspect of this debate I’m open to it being disussed in the comment section, however there are some interesting point in the articles given so do read them, never the less.
Since email won’t work to notify you, please check back here and continue checking back. Will finish reading the articles, but it will take at least a few days.
Your first post on this blog, under “Too Young for Rights?,” was a reply to a mathematical argument by Anon Y Mous. He is now going by the name ignorance_is_curable, and has replied to what you wrote, but has replied on the Secular Pro-Life website:
http://blog.secularprolife.org/2015/02/abortion-as-symptom-of-social-ill.html#comment-1883662563
At that link, see the end of his long “Regarding a human zygote” post.
“TRUE, but the key word there is ‘can’. Other sums of the infinitely small end up still equalling Zero.”
Indeed, but recall your latter comment.
“My argument is entirely consistent. EITHER sitting in the chair involves experiencing zero pain, OR it involves experiencing greater-than-zero pain, during each NOW/instant of sitting. YOUR description of “time” implies “zero pain”. Mathematically, zero experiences of pain per instant sums up to a zero total pain-experience, for the totality of instants. Therefore it doesn’t matter in the least when or how long you sit in that chair, IF your description is correct. THAT is the Logic (and the calculus!) of the situation. You are trying to confuse that with stuff about Future and/or Past, but I’m not letting you get away with it!”
I’m not sure if you’re claim is even wrong… (in the Wolfgang Pauli’s sense). It seems to me that you’re confusing zero with a infinitely small value and instants with infinitely small time intervals.
“And the context is important; we don’t yet know whether Time is a continuum or is quantized. If it is quantized, then it simply becomes WRONG to talk about zero-size slices of Time.”
Quantization of time does not imply that talk about infinitely small sizes of time is wrong or that time isn’t continuous…
“The discussion should be tabled until we have the relevant facts.”
There probably aren’t any relevant facts that have implications on this moral question… The relevant facts are those of how we as biological organisms experience time, not what is the true physical nature of time. So let’s just drop it.
This is a reply to your March 3, 2015 at 6:29 pm post.
Thanks. I’m working on understanding the science of it. This much I can understand: “The relevant facts are those of how we as biological organisms experience time, not what is the true physical nature of time.” That seems very well expressed.
Meanwhile, Anon Y Mous / ignorance_Is_curable said on the other page that he would not put a copy of his reply here on this page. And I stopped talking to him there due to some rudeness of his. So if you would like him to see your reply before you both drop the matter, you would have to put a copy of your reply on that other page.
“In the build-up to the abolition of slavery in the US, many people intuited that slavery was wrong; but the fact that slavery was ultimately abolished doesn’t mean that it was ever proved logically to be wrong. The abolitionist intuition was not proven; it prevailed.”
I see the point. Just because a view is believed by the majority and eventually wins in the end does not mean that it was the “correct” view. This is an important truth that applies to so many debates of truth and morality.
BTW, I am pro-life. I google searched for this post after you mentioned it in a youtube comment.
Thanks for your comment.
I’d be very interested in whether you agree with me about why it is important to understand this matter. I tried to explore “why” in my points 1-5 near the end. I could now summarize those 5 points in this way:
“When we understand better the roles played by intuition and logic in arriving at correct moral principles, we will understand that what we are really seeking is a correct moral intuition that already exists in us. Once we understand what we are seeking (a correct pre-logical inner conviction of right and wrong, not a logical proof), we will be better equipped to find it. The final result will be that we lead our lives with more correct moral principles.”
I think that if we follow this process wherever it may lead, it will lead us to the best possible moral principles whatever they may be. In the context of abortion, my personal guess is that those principles will be pro-life principles. I didn’t state that in the “Moral Intuition” post, but did say a little about it in another post, “Dismantling the Bodily-Rights Argument without Using the Responsibility Argument.” However, I think that we should be ready to follow the process wherever it may lead.
Acyutananda
Pingback: Dismantling the Bodily-Rights Argument without Using the Responsibility Argument | No Termination without Representation
Pingback: Bodily Rights – the Concept | No Termination without Representation
Pingback: What’s Wrong with Killing? | No Termination without Representation
Pingback: The Psychological Morass of the Abortion Issue | No Termination without Representation
In July 2017 there was some discussion on the Equal Rights Institute’s Facebook page about the epistemic value of moral intutions.
Here’s the comment transferred over from the Facebook thread. I agree the notifications are unreliable on there and that skipping between posts and skirting around topics is not all that helpful. E-mail notification of a post on a discussion here is probably easy enough and could flow for a longer period with more relaxed response times than on Facebook. It’s interesting to dig through the positions on this. I added the link to my phone’s reader software so maybe it’s chopped off the appendices.
I’d strongly contest that we wouldn’t even know right and wrong exist without moral intuitions and the unconscious is superior in moral epistemology. I’m with Sidgwick that moral truth is out there and objective from the ‘point of view of the universe’. There’s no reason to assume intuitive processes are superior at ascertaining it than they are at ascertaining other forms of truth. Much as I like him, this emotivist account of morality I take to be one of Hume’s unfortunate legacies. I don’t see why the correctness of claims like ‘the greatest good of the greatest number’ relies on anything intuitive anymore than apprehending various a priori truths does. You rationally apprehend than there are no unmarried bachelors you don’t intuit it. I contend it’s something similar with moral truth. Even if you don’t think it’s a deductive matter from first principles and take more of a reflexive equilibrium view of harmonising intuitions about particular cases to form principles and rules as it could be argued is the majority position in modern ethics that still makes intuitions very much defeasible in the light of other considerations and not a remarkable form of access to the incontrovertible and absolute moral truth. I’ve read most of that article now BTW and took a few notes but I don’t really think it addressed this possibility.
I do take psychological consequences to be all that matters, any bad consequence has to bottom out in the conscious experience of something so yeah the prefix is I guess redundant. This comes back to whether the biological organism is identical to the conscious entity for which there are psychological consequences. I contend not and that the entity with the moral status is psychological in nature and not reducible to biology. This makes abortion prior to consciousness pretty much tantamount to using contraception in terms of depriving an entity of conscious life.
Things start to get unfalsifiable verging on supernaturalistic when things turn to self-deception type undetectable harm type arguments of the ‘when she destroys a pregnancy, she is destroying herself’ type. To consistently reject population level well-being data would be to make cross-cultural comparison of societal health and individual well-being impossible and I certainly don’t accept that it isn’t a valid and useful measure in that context. As for whether it’s an innate and not cultural response (and also one that can’t be encultured over to the benefit of all). Further even if these nebulous impacts do exist why be confident they’re all bad? I could speculate about an enhanced sense of autonomy and power which makes a post-abortive woman less likely to be pushed around in her everyday life resulting from the unconscious impact of an abortion where she did what she wanted. I’m open to the idea there is an unavoidable innate negative impact of abortion (more plausible with later term surgical abortion) but I’m highly sceptical that cultural influences aren’t much more powerfully able to override it, and still less convinced that the negative impact of having and raising or putting up for adoption a child you didn’t want could be rendered less negatively impacting than it.
You could indeed say that people are only OK about abortion because they’re brainwashed into it in the same way Klansmen are racism. My point is not that the psychological consequences for Klansmen or aborting women determine whether or not lynching or abortion is morally acceptable all considered though. I’m looking at the psychological consequences of abortion under various conditions irrespective of the moral truth of its (im)permissibly. As you’ve alluded to it’s unlikely that the psychological consequences of actions cut through enculturation to reflect objective moral truths (even less likely on my account of morality than yours I suspect) rather than just what people and cultures believe to be morally true. My point is that culture can render it harmless – or at least much less harmful – and less harm is better than more. So if you bracket off the possible wrongs of lynching or abortion deriving from the moral status and entitlements of blacks or fetuses, happier Klansmen and aborting women are morally better than unhappy ones. Of course the harm to blacks of lynchings is sufficient to outweigh the well-being gained by Klansmen who are racist even without the mutual benefits of transcending racism being taken into account. With abortion I’d deny there’s the kind of entity that can be harmed in most cases (and where there is there’s plausibly a good case that the overall balance of interests justifies the killing of the fetus but forget that bit for now). I seriously doubt that a society which transcends accepting abortion would see benefits from it like one that transcends racism would.
Thanks.
Before we discuss which would benefit society more, transcending the acceptance of abortion or transcending racism, and before we talk about cutting through enculturation to reflect objective moral truths, let’s continue only about intuitions and the related epistemology, because that will be quite enough to try to make progress on.
First of all, I think that psychology, which is a science, overlaps considerably with moral epistemology. “Moral Intuition, Logic, and the Abortion Debate” confines itself to that overlap. In that essay I don’t venture into moral epistemology that is not also psychology. So though I have little formal background in Western philosophy, I don’t think I’m getting into moral epistemology that is over my head, unless I’m also getting into psychology that is over my head. My views about psychology could be wrong. But if my arguments can be defeated, either they have to be defeated based on logical flaws, or the psychological claims that they’re based on have to be debunked as science, in a scientific way.
My thinking has evolved since I first wrote the essay 3 years ago, and most of the new thinking has gone into the appendices at the end where it didn’t most logically belong. The central argument of the original essay was that the correctness of correct moral intuitions cannot be logically proved. If I were to redo the whole thing, I would start by establishing the existence of correct moral intuitions (touched on in the essay where I talk about psychological health), and by arguing that they are ultimately the only window (form of access) to moral truth. In the essay I touched on the latter where I said, “The caring part of our minds cannot use logic, and the logical part cannot care,” but I now think that my best argument for the latter may be Appendix B.
You have written, “I’d strongly contest. . . . and not a remarkable form of access to the incontrovertible and absolute moral truth,” but specifically how does any of that, or anything else, expose flaws in Appendix B? (Please consider this the main question that I’d like to focus on.)
“You rationally apprehend than there are no unmarried bachelors you don’t intuit it.”
Well, you can rationally apprehend it by appealing to a rule such as “A cannot be not A” and then rationally concluding that unmarried bachelors would be a case of A being not A. But how is it that “A cannot be not A” satisfies us as true? Do we arrive at “A cannot be not A” through a prior rational process, or does it just satisfy us because it satisfies us?
“Even if you . . . take more of a refle[ct]ive equilibrium view of harmonising intuitions about particular cases to form principles and rules . . . that still makes intuitions very much defeasible in the light of other considerations . . .”
Are those other considerations the principles and rules that are derivative of intuitions in the first place?
A P.S. to Appendix B: Trying to reason out what the word “wrong” means would be like trying to reason out what the word “green” means. It might be best to call what it means a kind of qualia.
Part of the “wrong” sensation that we experience is the negativity of it. Without the “wrong” sensation, we might observe that a person is causing untold unpleasant consequences, but merely with that utilitarian observation we would have no notion of the evil in the person’s mind or of the fact that that evil is contracting the person’s mind and preventing its expansion, or the way in which it is doing that.
I just heard a lecture by Jonathan Haidt, who researches in moral psychology.
Jonathan Haidt lecture on morality at Stanford
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=1u-ahvx3pkc
He says (in the Q&A at the end) that our rational faculty has no capacity for empathy. I think that empathy is a pre-logical sensation, a kind of qualia, and I think that the sense of right and wrong is also.
In the comments under the May 15, 2019 “The zygote is the beginning of the human life cycle: everyday examples” blog post on the Secular Pro-Life blog, I referred to “Moral Intuition, Logic, and the Abortion Debate,” and Jonathan F.V. replied to me. However, his reply was marked as spam by the Disqus software for some reason. Here is his reply:
Hi, thanks for your reply, and my apologies for replying late. I got busy and couldn’t look into it right away. As for the comment marked as spam, it was probably mine, but it wasn’t anything that didn’t get posted (I tried replying, a Captcha showed, but it wasn’t readable due to the paragraphs becoming too narrow on the secular pro-life website, so I copied it and reposted it from Discus).
I have read Appendix D, and I think it was interesting. Here are the comments I have regarding it.
While I personally listen to my intuitions for many things in my life, before taking important decisions (or before making an argument for something important, or before sharing my thoughts), I do my best to understand my intuitions and assess whether or not they are logically correct based on a variety of things. If you ask me why I think something is correct or incorrect and I have a strong stance about it, I should be able to communicate and explain why. For reasons like this one, I would not rely on intuitions, but I would certain consider them, especially if my decision impacts people other than myself.
While it is fine to have your own morality and to listen to your intuitions, if you are unable to make others understand them and if you are unable to communicate them properly because transcending experiences tend to be limited to individuals, then you cannot convince others your moral intuition is correct, you can only convince them you had a moral intuition. I don’t deny transcending experiences at all, I do believe they happen. But the nature of that experience doesn’t indicate anything about it’s correctness or its truth.
I had an online friend who I used to collaborate with on some projects, and with whom I regularly shared news of each other. One day, he started posting religious messages on his website, which was in big part intended for business. A little bit alarmed, I asked him to tell me what made him start believing in god, while he used to hold no religious beliefs. Essentially (to be brief), he told me that he came home a couple days earlier. His girlfriend was sitting on the bed, and she tol d him very seriously: “I’m sorry, but I don’t think we can stay together if you don’t become a Christian and marry me.” Instead of walking away, heartbroken, like I would have, he decided to give it a shot. At first, he didn’t believe, but she showed him a bunch of videos about cool biblical characters he could identify with. He still didn’t believe, but in a last ditch effort, he decided to stay up for many days and pray until he would feel god’s presence. Which he eventually did. I don’t doubt that he felt god’s presence. But I do not think that what he felt really was god’s presence. He had simply worked really, really hard at convincing himself. I don’t think his experience is indicative of any deeper truths than what was his experience itself.
Would they converge completely independently, or would they converge as they spend time together? Many people could have very strong moral intuitions, but some of them could diverge. The moral intuitions that are the most universal tend to be those that allow humans to live in society, such as repulsion for murder and violence in general, and compassion for others, which pushes us to care for one an other.
I agree that people who rely on a transcendent experience cannot convince others through rational processes. Thus, transcendent experiences should not be used to establish rules over others. Anyone who is being imposed a limit for which they can receive no explanation will see that limit as arbitrary. I do not intend to respect any rules I see as being arbitrary, nor do I intend to impose any rules I cannot explain to others. I think you are entitled to your opinion on the issue of abortion, but relying on intuitions that cannot be discussed rationally is a bit of a debate killer. I think that you did a good job of describing part of where your own morality comes from, but that doesn’t tell me why I should agree with you. I think that if you seeked to make laws based on your position, you couldn’t do it without being authoritarian, which makes me hope your aim is to discuss and convince people not to have abortions, but not legally ban it.
My reply to him:
Thanks for reading Appendix D and giving it some thought.
You may have gotten the impression that I think people necessarily find their moral intuitions during transcendent experiences. While I think that is possible, that is not the relation between moral intuitions and transcendent experiences that I was trying to describe. First it might be good to have a concrete example of a transcendent experience. Neuroscientist Sam Harris has described a transcendent experience of his:
Harris apparently did not find any moral intuitions during the experience he describes, and as I have said, I do not think people necessarily find their moral intuitions during transcendent experiences. They may find them at any time, but are especially likely to find them when they have to confront some real or imaginary situation that presents a moral dilemma.
So what IS the relationship that I think exists between transcendent experiences and moral intuitions, especially correct moral intuitions?
I think that if we find a correct moral intuition in ourselves and adhere to it in our actions, that will give us a clean conscience and peace of mind. If one’s mind is already peaceful (not uneasily remembering one’s past wrong actions, consciously or subconsciously), then one is in a good position, either through intentional meditation efforts or just good luck, for “the sense of being a separate self — an ‘I’ or a ‘me'” — to vanish, as happened with Harris.
And transcendent experiences are the greatest good in life. In the above, Harris uses the word “blissful,” and elsewhere he has agreed with me about the greatest good. And I am saying that transcendent experiences are a reward we will likely get for finding correct moral intuitions in ourselves and adhering to them in our actions – but not that we will necessarily find those correct moral intuition during transcendent experiences.
So now we have objective criteria for determining which moral intuitions (along with the moral principles they support) are correct. Or at least we would have objective criteria if we could reach a consensus that transcendent experiences are the greatest good in life, and that the power to facilitate such experiences makes moral intuitions/principles correct – and if we could measure people’s transcendent experiences, and confirm that they are facilitated by following certain moral principles (which neuroscience may be able to do some day).
I have added to my Appendix D:
“An objective moral truth is a moral intuition which, if we find it in ourselves and adhere to it in our actions, will help us to attain transcendent experiences, the greatest good in life.”
“If you ask me why I think something is correct or incorrect and I have a strong stance about it, I should be able to communicate and explain why.”
I don’t think I agree with this, but will discuss it later.
“I don’t think his experience is indicative of any deeper truths than what was his experience itself.”
You’re probably right about him, but that doesn’t mean that others have not achieved genuine moral development. I think it just means there are pitfalls.
“Would they converge completely independently”
I think they would.
“I agree that people who rely on a transcendent experience cannot convince others through rational processes. Thus, transcendent experiences should not be used to establish rules over others. Anyone who is being imposed a limit for which they can receive no explanation will see that limit as arbitrary. I do not intend to respect any rules I see as being arbitrary, nor do I intend to impose any rules I cannot explain to others.”
I don’t think there’s any “thus.” I don’t see how your second sentence follows from your first. You try to back it up with your third and fourth. But to keep this short, let me just ask you whether you are sure about your last clause, “nor do I intend to impose any rules I cannot explain to others.” From your writing I would guess you’re American or Canadian. In group must prevail over the views of another. In Canada several years ago, an immigrant couple were convicted of the “honor killing” of their daughter. Wouldn’t you have supported their conviction? Yet the couple sincerely believed that it was their moral duty, maybe religious duty, to kill their daughter. I don’t think you would have been able to convince them through any rational process. Nevertheless, the majority in Canada — fortunately, in the case of that issue, unfortunately perhaps on other issues — impose their views on the minority. Sometimes it is good to impose views. In order for any society with any diversity to hold together, the views of one group must prevail over the views of another.